Article published In:
Pragmatics & Cognition
Vol. 22:3 (2014) ► pp.352372
References
Bach, K., & Harnish, R
(1979) Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Burge, T
(1989) Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–121. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1986a) Individualism and psychology. The Philosophical Review, 95(1), 3–45. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1986b) Cartesian error and the objectivity of perception. In S. Merril (Ed.), The Contents of Thought. Tucson: University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F
(1997) Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Grice, P
(1957) Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 661, 377–388. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, D
(1978) Dthat. Syntax and Semantics, 91, 221–243.Google Scholar
Kripke, S
(1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R
(1984) Language, thought, and other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
(2005) Language: A Biological Model. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H
(1975) The meaning of meaning. Reprinted in H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1976 DOI: DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1996) Introduction. In A. Pessin & S. Goldberg (Eds.), The Twin Earth Chronicles: 20 Years of Reflections on Hilary Putnam’s “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’.” New York: M. E. Sharpe.Google Scholar
Searle, J
(1963/1991) What is a speech act? Reprinted in S. Davis (Ed.), Pragmatics (pp. 254–264). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(1975/1991) Indirect speech acts. Reprinted in S. Davis (Ed.), Pragmatics (pp. 265–277). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(1983) Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar