Part of
Essays on Linguistic Realism
Edited by Christina Behme and Martin Neef
[Studies in Language Companion Series 196] 2018
► pp. 235254
References
Bach, Kent
1994Conversational impliciture. Mind & Language 9: 124–162. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David
1996The Conscious Mind. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald
1967Truth and meaning. Synthese 17: 304–323; reprinted in Davidson (2001). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2001Inquiries Into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit
2007Semantic Relationism. Malden MA: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Grice, Paul
1967Logic and conversation (given in 1967 as the William James lectures at Harvard University). In Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 3: Speech Acts, Peter Cole & Jerry L. Morgan (eds), 41–58. New York NY: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul
1979A puzzle about belief. In Meaning and Use, Avishai Margalit (ed.), 239–283. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary
1970Is semantics possible? Metaphilosophy 1(3): 187–201; reprinted in Putnam (1975a). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1975aPhilosophical Papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
1975bThe meaning of ‘meaning’. In Language, Mind, and Knowledge [Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7], Keith Gunderson (ed.), 131–193. Minneapolis MN: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Putnam (1975a).Google Scholar
Salmon, Nathan
2012Recurrence. Philosophical Studies 159: 407–441. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Soames, Scott
1987Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. Philosophical Topics 15: 44–87. Reprinted in Soames (2009c). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2002Beyond Rigidity. Oxford: OUP. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2005Reference and Description. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
2006Understanding assertion. In Content and Modality, Judith Thomson & Alex Byrne (eds), 222–250. Oxford: OUP. Reprinted in Soames 2009c.Google Scholar
2008aDrawing the line between meaning and implicature – and relating both to assertion. Nous 42: 529–554. Reprinted in Soames (2009b). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2008bWhy propositions can’t be sets of truth-supporting circumstances. Journal of Philosophical Logic 37: 267–276. Reprinted in Soames (2009c). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2009aThe gap between meaning and assertion: Why what we literally say often differs from what our words literally mean. In Soames (2009b), 278–297.Google Scholar
2009bPhilosophical Essays, Vol. 1. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
2009cPhilosophical Essays, Vol. 2. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
2010aWhat is Meaning? Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2010bPhilosophy of Language. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2012Two versions of Millianism. In Reference and Referring, Topics in Philosophy, Vol. 10, Joseph Campbell, Michael O’Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds), 83–118. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press. Reprinted in Soames (2014).Google Scholar
2014Analytic Philosophy in America. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
2015Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert
1978Assertion. In Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 9: Pragmatics, Peter Cole (ed.), 315–322. New York NY: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Cited by

Cited by 2 other publications

Hodgson, Thomas
2021. Act‐type theories of propositions. Philosophy Compass 16:11 DOI logo
Soames, Scott
2022. Anti-descriptivism 2.0. Philosophical Studies 179:3  pp. 977 ff. DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 22 april 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.