References
Bechtel, W
(2006) Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
(2008) Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York, NY: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A
(2002) Connectionism and the mind: Parallel processing, dynamics, and evolution in networks (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brown, M.E., & Swallowe, G.E
(1981) The thermal decomposition of the silver (I) and mercury (II) salts of 5-nitrotetrazole and of mercury (II) fulminate. Thermochimica Acta, 49(2–3), 333–349. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bunge, M
(1997) Mechanism and explanation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27(4), 410–416. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D.J
(1996) The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M
(1995) The engine of reason, the seat of the soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Craver, C.F
(2001) Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 53–74. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2007) Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R
(1975) Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72(20), 741–765. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Faust, W.L
(1989) Explosive molecular ionic crystals. Science, 245(4913), 37–42. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A
(1974) Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1989) Making mind matter more. Philosophical Topics, 17(1), 59–79. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fries, P., Nikolić, D., & Singer, W
(2007) The gamma cycle. Trends in Neurosciences, 30(7), 309–116. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Glennan, S
(2002) Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69(S3), S342–S353. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C.G
(1966) Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.Google Scholar
Köhler, W
(1920) Die physischen Gestalten in Ruhe und im stationären Zustand. Braunschweig: Vieweg und Sohn. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kurzer, F
(2000) Fulminic acid in the history of organic chemistry. Journal of Chemical Education, 77(7), 851–857. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lamme, V.A.F
(2000) Neural mechanisms of visual awareness: A linking proposition. Brain and Mind, 1(3), 385–406. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2004) Separate neural definitions of visual consciousness and visual attention; A case for phenomenal awareness. Neural Networks, 17(5–6), 861–872. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Llinás, R., Ribary, U., Contreras, D., & Pedroarena, C
(1998) The neuronal basis for consciousness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 353(1377), 1841–1849. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C.F
(2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
McGinn, C
(1991) The problem of consciousness: Essays toward a resolution. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Miller, S.M
(2007) On the correlation/constitution distinction problem (and other hard problems) in the scientific study of consciousness. Acta Neuropsychiatrica, 19(3), 159–76. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T
(1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Newman, J
(1995) Thalamic contributions to attention and consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 4(2), 172–193. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
O’Brien, G., & Opie, J
(1998) The disunity of consciousness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76(3), 378–395. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1999) A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(1), 127–148. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2000) Disunity defended: A reply to Bayne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 255–263. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H
(1958) Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, Vol. 2, Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem (pp.3–36). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minneapolis Press.Google Scholar
Priestley, J
(1775) The history and present status of electricity, with original experiments, Vol. 1 (3rd ed.). London, UK: C. Bathurst & T. Lowndes, et al.Google Scholar
Revonsuo, A
(2006) Inner presence: Consciousness as a biological phenomenon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
(2010) Consciousness: The science of subjectivity. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Robertson, T
(2008) Essential vs. accidental properties. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 edition). Retrieved from [URL]
Salmon, W.C
(1978) Why ask, “Why?”? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 51(6), 683–705. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Singer, W
(1999) Neuronal synchrony: A versatile code for the definition of relations? Neuron, 24(1), 49–65. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2007) Binding by synchrony. Scholarpedia, 2(12), 1657. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Smart, J.J.C
(1959) Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Tononi, G
(2004) An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neuroscience, 5, 42. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2008) Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto. Biological Bulletin, 215(3), 216–242. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Tononi, G., & Koch, C
(2008) The neural correlates of consciousness: An update. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1124, 239–261. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Varela, F., Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., & Martinerie, J
(2001) The brainweb: Phase synchronization and large-scale integration. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2(4), 229–239. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Waldmann, R., Chamigny, G., Bassilana, F., Heurteaux, C., & Lazdunski, M
(1997) A proton-gated cation channel involved in acid-sensing. Nature, 386(6621), 173–177. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Woodward, J
(1989) The causal mechanical model of explanation. In P. Kitcher & W.C. Salmon (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, Vol. 13, Scientific explanation (pp.357–383). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minneapolis Press.Google Scholar
Zeki, S., & Bartels, A
(1999) Toward a theory of visual consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 8(2), 225–259. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cited by

Cited by 1 other publications

Kob, Lukas
2023. Exploring the role of structuralist methodology in the neuroscience of consciousness: a defense and analysis. Neuroscience of Consciousness 2023:1 DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 20 april 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.